4.19. Lecture 19

4.19.1. Morphisms between permutation modules

We aim to complete the proof of Theorem 4.17.12 by showing that (π,𝒮λ)(\pi,{\mathcal{S}}^{\lambda}) and (π,𝒮μ)(\pi,{\mathcal{S}}^{\mu}) are non-isomorphic representations of SnS_{n} if λμ\lambda\neq\mu.

To do this, we introduce a partial order \unlhd on the set of all Young diagrams of size nn.

Definition 4.19.1.

Let λ,μn\lambda,\mu\vdash n. We write λμ\lambda\unlhd\mu if

i=1mλii=1mμi,\sum_{i=1}^{m}\lambda_{i}\leq\sum_{i=1}^{m}\mu_{i},

for all 1mmin{|λ|,|μ|}1\leq m\leq\min\{|\lambda|,|\mu|\}.

Proposition 4.19.2.

The relation \unlhd defines a partial order on the set of all Young diagrams of size nn.

Proof.

This is Problem 4.19.3 (not examinable). ∎

Example 4.19.3.

For the partitions of 66, we have

(4,2)(5,1)(6),(4,2)\unlhd(5,1)\unlhd(6),

and

(3,2,1)(4,1,1)(4,2),(3,2,1)\unlhd(4,1,1)\unlhd(4,2),

as well as

(3,2,1)(3,3)(4,2).(3,2,1)\unlhd(3,3)\unlhd(4,2).

Observe that we (3,3)(4,1,1)(3,3)\not\unlhd(4,1,1), since 4+1<3+34+1<3+3, but also (4,1,1)(3,3)(4,1,1)\not\unlhd(3,3), since 3<43<4.

Proposition 4.19.4.

Let λ,μn\lambda,\mu\vdash n. Suppose that there exists t𝐘𝐓λt\in\mathbf{YT}^{\lambda} such that the morphism

Pt=σC(t)sgn(σ)π(σ)P_{t}=\sum_{\sigma\in C(t)}\operatorname{sgn}(\sigma)\pi(\sigma)

on μ{\mathcal{M}}^{\mu} is non-zero. Then μλ\mu\unlhd\lambda.

Proof.

If Pt0P_{t}\neq 0, then there exists a Young tableau ss of shape μ\mu such that Pt[s]0P_{t}[s]\neq 0. Let ii and jj be two numbers from the same row of ss. If ii and jj were in the same column of tt, then (ij)C(t)(ij)\in C(t), and in a similar way to the proof of Proposition 4.18.4, writing H=(ij)={e,(ij)}H=\langle(ij)\rangle=\{e,(ij)\} and letting r1,,rmC(t)r_{1},\ldots,r_{m}\in C(t) be a set of representatives for C(t)/HC(t)/H (i.e. C(t)=r1Hr2HrmHC(t)=r_{1}H\sqcup r_{2}H\sqcup\ldots\sqcup r_{m}H), we would then have

Pt[s]=jπ(rj)(π(e)π(ij))[s]=0.P_{t}[s]=\sum_{j}\pi(r_{j})\big{(}\pi(e)-\pi(ij)\big{)}[s]=0.

Thus any two numbers from the same row of ss are in different columns of tt. There are μ1\mu_{1} numbers in the first row of ss, which must be placed into different columns of tt; tt has λ1\lambda_{1} columns, hence μ1λ1\mu_{1}\leq\lambda_{1}. After placing out the numbers from the first row, we then must place out the μ2\mu_{2} numbers into the columns of tt. Having already placed out the numbers of the first row of ss, there are then (λ1μ1)+λ2(\lambda_{1}-\mu_{1})+\lambda_{2} columns available to put them in, hence μ2(λ1μ1)+λ2\mu_{2}\leq(\lambda_{1}-\mu_{1})+\lambda_{2}, i.e. μ1+μ2λ1+λ2\mu_{1}+\mu_{2}\leq\lambda_{1}+\lambda_{2}. Proceeding in this manner gives μλ\mu\unlhd\lambda. ∎

Proposition 4.19.5.

If there exists an SnS_{n}-homomorphism from (π,λ)(\pi,{\mathcal{M}}^{\lambda}) to (π,μ)(\pi,{\mathcal{M}}^{\mu}) whose restriction to 𝒮λ{\mathcal{S}}^{\lambda} is non-zero, then μλ\mu\unlhd\lambda.

Proof.

Letting THomSn(λ,μ)T\in\operatorname{Hom}_{S_{n}}({\mathcal{M}}^{\lambda},{\mathcal{M}}^{\mu}) be such that T|𝒮λ0T|_{{\mathcal{S}}^{\lambda}}\neq 0, i.e. we can find one of the spanning vectors 𝐞t𝒮λ{\bf e}_{t}\in{\mathcal{S}}^{\lambda} such that T(𝐞t)0T({\bf e}_{t})\neq 0. Since 𝐞t=Pt[t]{\bf e}_{t}=P_{t}[t], we then have

0T(𝐞t)=T(Pt[t])=PtT([t]).0\neq T({\bf e}_{t})=T(P_{t}[t])=P_{t}T([t]).

The morphism PtP_{t} evaluated at T([t])μT([t])\in{\mathcal{M}}^{\mu} is non-zero, so by Proposition 4.19.4 μλ\mu\unlhd\lambda. ∎

Finishing the proof of Theorem 4.17.12.

Suppose that (π,𝒮λ)(\pi,{\mathcal{S}}^{\lambda}) and (π,𝒮μ)(\pi,{\mathcal{S}}^{\mu}) are isomorphic, with THomG(𝒮λ,𝒮μ)T\in\operatorname{Hom}_{G}({\mathcal{S}}^{\lambda},{\mathcal{S}}^{\mu}). We decompose λ{\mathcal{M}}^{\lambda} as

(π,λ)=(π,𝒮λ)(π,(𝒮λ)),(\pi,{\mathcal{M}}^{\lambda})=(\pi,{\mathcal{S}}^{\lambda})\oplus(\pi,({% \mathcal{S}}^{\lambda})^{\perp}),

and trivially extend TT to an morphism T~\widetilde{T} on all of λ{\mathcal{M}}^{\lambda} by setting it to zero on (𝒮λ)({\mathcal{S}}^{\lambda})^{\perp}, i.e.

T~(𝐯+𝐰):=T(𝐯)𝐯𝒮λ,𝐰(𝒮λ).\widetilde{T}({\bf v}+{\bf w}):=T({\bf v})\qquad\forall{\bf v}\in{\mathcal{S}}% ^{\lambda},\;{\bf w}\in({\mathcal{S}}^{\lambda})^{\perp}.

This is also a SnS_{n}-homomorphism since (π,(𝒮))(\pi,({\mathcal{S}})^{\perp}) is a subrepresentation. Since TT is non-zero, so is T~\widetilde{T}, allowing us to apply the Proposition 4.19.5 to get μλ\mu\unlhd\lambda. By symmetry (i.e. carrying out the same argument with T1T^{-1} in place of TT), we also have λμ\lambda\unlhd\mu, thus λ=μ\lambda=\mu. ∎

4.19.2. Standard Young Tableaux

Definition 4.19.6.

A Young tableau is said to be standard if the numbers in each row and column are increasing left to right and top to bottom.

The set of all standard Young tableaux of shape λ\lambda is denoted 𝐒𝐘𝐓λ\mathbf{SYT}^{\lambda}. We define

fλ=|𝐒𝐘𝐓λ|.f_{\lambda}=|\mathbf{SYT}^{\lambda}|.

We have the following combinatorial result which is a generalisation of the Robinson–Schensted correspondence (1938,1961).

Theorem 4.19.7 (Robinson–Schensted–Knuth correspondence, 1970).

There is a bijection between SnS_{n} and λn𝐒𝐘𝐓λ×𝐒𝐘𝐓λ\bigcup_{\lambda\vdash n}\mathbf{SYT}^{\lambda}\times\mathbf{SYT}^{\lambda}. In particular,

n!=λn(fλ)2.n!=\sum_{\lambda\vdash n}(f_{\lambda})^{2}.

We do not have the time to prove this here. A nice discussion for the interested reader can be found in Chapter 4 of Young Tableaux by William Fulton.

Theorem 4.19.8.

The set {𝐞t|t𝐒𝐘𝐓λ}\{{\bf e}_{t}\,|\,t\in\mathbf{SYT}^{\lambda}\} is a basis of 𝒮λ{\mathcal{S}}^{\lambda}.

Proof.

We will show that for each λn\lambda\vdash n, the set {𝐞t|t𝐒𝐘𝐓λ}\{{\bf e}_{t}\,|\,t\in\mathbf{SYT}^{\lambda}\} is linearly independent. From this, we then get that

dim(𝒮λ)|{𝐞t|t𝐒𝐘𝐓λ}|=fλ.\operatorname{dim}({\mathcal{S}}^{\lambda})\geq|\{{\bf e}_{t}\,|\,t\in\mathbf{% SYT}^{\lambda}\}|=f_{\lambda}.

By Theorem 1.6.6(ii), Theorem 4.17.12, and Theorem 4.19.7, we then have

n!=λndim(𝒮λ)2λn(fλ)2=n!,n!=\sum_{\lambda\vdash n}\operatorname{dim}({\mathcal{S}}^{\lambda})^{2}\geq% \sum_{\lambda\vdash n}(f_{\lambda})^{2}=n!,

which gives dim(𝒮λ)=fλ\operatorname{dim}({\mathcal{S}}^{\lambda})=f_{\lambda}, i.e. the set {𝐞t|t𝐒𝐘𝐓λ}\{{\bf e}_{t}\,|\,t\in\mathbf{SYT}^{\lambda}\} spans 𝒮λ{\mathcal{S}}^{\lambda}, and is therefore a basis.

So it remains to show that the 𝐞t{\bf e}_{t}, t𝐒𝐘𝐓λt\in\mathbf{SYT}^{\lambda}, are linearly independent. Before this, we need to introduce another order. ∎

Definition 4.19.9.

Define the relation \prec on 𝐘𝐓𝐃λ\mathbf{YTD}^{\lambda} as follows. We say [s][t][s]\prec[t] if there exists an 1in1\leq i\leq n such that for each j<ij<i we have jj in the same row in both [s][s] and [t][t] and ii appears in a row of [s][s] below the row it appears in [t][t].

Example 4.19.10.

The six elements of 𝐘𝐓𝐃(2,2)\mathbf{YTD}^{(2,2)} are

\ytableausetuptabloids\ytableaushort12,34,\ytableaushort13,24,\ytableaushort14,23,\ytableaushort34,12,\ytableaushort24,13,\ytableaushort23,14.\ytableausetup{tabloids}\ytableaushort{12,34},\quad\ytableaushort{13,24},\quad% \ytableaushort{14,23},\quad\ytableaushort{34,12},\quad\ytableaushort{24,13},% \quad\ytableaushort{23,14}.

The order of these elements is

\ytableausetuptabloids\ytableaushort34,12\ytableaushort24,13\ytableaushort23,14\ytableaushort14,23\ytableaushort13,24\ytableaushort12,34.\ytableausetup{tabloids}\ytableaushort{34,12}\prec\ytableaushort{24,13}\prec% \ytableaushort{23,14}\prec\ytableaushort{14,23}\prec\ytableaushort{13,24}\prec% \ytableaushort{12,34}.
Proposition 4.19.11.

The relation \prec defines a total order on 𝐘𝐓𝐃λ\mathbf{YTD}^{\lambda}

Proof.

This is Problem 4.19.3 (not examinable). ∎

Lemma 4.19.12.

For any t𝐒𝐘𝐓λt\in\mathbf{SYT}^{\lambda} we have [σt][t][\sigma\cdot t]\prec[t] for all σC(t){e}\sigma\in C(t)\setminus\{e\}.

Proof.

Given σC(t){e}\sigma\in C(t)\setminus\{e\}, let ii be the smallest number in {1,,n}\{1,\ldots,n\} such that ii is in a different position in σt\sigma\cdot t than in tt. Since ii is moved to a place in the same column, it must be moved down to a lower row, since otherwise it would displace a number above it in the same column, which is necessarily smaller than ii, as tt is standard. This would contradict the minimality in the choice of ii. Thus, for every j<ij<i, [σt][\sigma\cdot t] and [t][t] have jj in the same row, and [σt][\sigma\cdot t] has ii in a lower row, hence [σt][t][\sigma\cdot t]\prec[t]. ∎

Finishing the proof of Theorem 4.19.8.

Suppose that {𝐞t|t𝐒𝐘𝐓λ}\{{\bf e}_{t}\,|\,t\in\mathbf{SYT}^{\lambda}\} is linearly dependent. Then there exist ztz_{t} (not all zero) such that

t𝐒𝐘𝐓λzt𝐞t=0.\sum_{t\in\mathbf{SYT}^{\lambda}}z_{t}{\bf e}_{t}=0. (4.19.13)

Suppose t0𝐒𝐘𝐓λt_{0}\in\mathbf{SYT}^{\lambda} such that [t0][t_{0}] is maximal among all [t][t] where zt0z_{t}\neq 0. Since the tabloids form a basis of λ{\mathcal{M}}^{\lambda}, once all the 𝐞t{\bf e}_{t} with non-zero ztz_{t} have been expanded into tabloids, the coefficient in front of [t0][t_{0}] must be zero. But [t0][t_{0}] cannot appear as a component in any of the other 𝐞t{\bf e}_{t}, since by assumption [t][t0][t]\prec[t_{0}], hence by Lemma 4.19.12, we have [s][t][t0][s]\prec[t]\prec[t_{0}] for any [s][s] a component of [𝐞t][{\bf e}_{t}]. Thus zt0=0z_{t_{0}}=0, a contradiction. ∎

4.19.3. Exercises

.

Problem 95. Verify that \unlhd is a partial order on the set of partitions of nn (not examinable).

Problem 96. Verify that \prec is a strict total order on 𝐘𝐓𝐃λ\mathbf{YTD}^{\lambda} (not examinable).

Problem 97. Show that if s,t𝐒𝐘𝐓λs,t\in\mathbf{SYT}^{\lambda}, then [s][t][s]\neq[t] if and only if sts\neq t.

Problem 98. Use Proposition 4.19.5 to compute the characters of (π,𝒮(4,2))(\pi,{\mathcal{S}}^{(4,2)}) and then (π,𝒮(3,3))(\pi,{\mathcal{S}}^{(3,3)}) Challenging! Hint: Proposition 4.19.5 puts a restriction on the shapes of the 𝒮λ{\mathcal{S}}^{\lambda} that can appear as subrepresentations of (4,2){\mathcal{M}}^{(4,2)} and (3,3){\mathcal{M}}^{(3,3)}.